Semana 14: Controlling Corruption Through Collective Action,
Mungiu-Pippidi
Central Idea: “In order to place effective
checks on these officials [who act as patrons or gatekeepers for corruption in
patrimonial regimes], thereby creating real accountability, there must exist at
the grassroots level an active and enlightened citizenry rather than simply
dependent clients or disempowered individuals” (103).
·
“Democratization
is increasingly producing a new type of regime—one in which rulers who
monopolize power and treat the state as their own patrimony are succeeded by
competing political groupings or parties that practice similarly nonuniversal
allocation of public resources based on patronage, nepotism, and the exchange
of favors. (…) Despite the presence of
political pluralism and contested elections in these societies, ethical
universalism fails to take hold as the main rule of the game, and winners
of the political process, in turn, treat the state as the major source of
spoils, feeding off the public resources that they divert toward their clients”
(101). Political competition in itself (maybe also economic competition) does
not in itself solve particularism, patrimonialism or corruption. Competition
does not ensure that a set of rules oriented at maximum social welfare will
exist or even develop.
·
“It
seems that ethical universalism becomes an
institution (a widespread norm endorsed by the majority) rather than a mere
ideology of the enlightened when 1) a significant part of society shares the
belief in the superiority of ethical universalism over particularism as a mode
of governance, and 2) enough individuals are also willing to act on this belief
to make it a reality. This does not necessarily require an absolute
majority, but rather a majority of active public opinion, including a fraction
of the elite” (104). Public opinion (defined as that of the media and an active
citizenry) can shape what the rules are when they act as watchdogs and are not
relegated to being clients of the government. Mungiu-Pippidi focuses on what
she considers to be a set of rules called “ethical universalism”, but it may be
more a matter of justice than of ethics, as she also calls it “an optimal
equilibrium that maximizes social welfare” (109).
·
Civil society must “have the
permanent capability to exercise normative constraints, and not be forced to
rely solely on the vertical accountability provided by elections” (109) through the extensive use of
civil associations and political participation. In parallel, “the media must be pluralistic and must
carry out their watchdog duties effectively and credibly in order to generate
normative constraints. The media must promote ethical universalism as the
chief principle of governance and denounce governments captured by private
interests” (110). This ensures that there is one set of rules for everyone, and
that the government cannot rely on its authority or clientelistic relationships
with the citizenry or the media to circumvent them.
The “normative
constraints” cited by Mungiu-Pippidi are (103-104):
·
Values: “A prevailing social norm of ethical
universalism based on values such as fairness and honesty”
·
Social capital: “A widespread habit of engaging in
formal or informal collective action around shared interests, purposes, and
values”
·
Civil society: “A dense network of voluntary
associations (including the NGOs in the Western understanding of the term, but
also unions, religious groups, and the like)”
·
Civic culture: “Sustained participation and
political engagement of the people, for instance through the media or social
movements”
Mungiu-Pippidi tests her central thesis
empirically and finds a “significant positive relationship between control of
corruption and:
·
“the
number of associations (CSOs) per capita that explains 54% of the total
variation, controlling for either human development or GDP per capita”
·
“freedom
of the press” (67%), via Freedom House’s index
·
“Number
of internet connections” (71%), used as an indicator of individual autonomy and
access to information
·
“Protestantism
is the major religious denomination” (61%), which seems to be relevant due to
its “egalitarian ethos, which may have worked indirectly to support a general
orientation toward ethical universalism, literacy, and the promotion of
individualism”.
·
Joined
in an OLS regression, these four variables account for “nearly 78% of the
cases” and 84% “when outliers are eliminated” (107).
These percentages refer to how much of the
variation in countries’ measure in the World Bank Institute’s control of
corruption indicator can be traced to these four characteristics, both
individually and as a group.
Mungiu-Pippidi then goes on to explain the
problems faced by external donors when financing anticorruption projects in
developing countries. These are:
·
Insufficient
concreteness: “Far too many projects deal with corruption in general, with a
focus on “raising awareness”, while only a handful directly attack corruption
in a specific organization or branch of government” (113).
·
Poor
contextualization: “To challenge corruption, one must understand how it works
in a specific environment. Importing anticorruption policies from developed to
less-developed countries, where institutional fit is poor, cannot succeed”
(113).
·
Confusion
between civil society’s role as a watchdog over the government and a deliverer
of services for that same government: “If civil society is funded by the
government or asked by its donors to carry out joint programs with the
government that it is supposed to monitor, it risks jeopardizing its critical
oversight role, and a client-patron relationship may emerge instead” (113).
·
Lack
of a local focus: “As normative constraints in corrupt societies are more often
exercised against whistleblowers than against corrupt officials, it is
essential that donor groups provide political support and take their cues from
local actors rather than trying themselves to direct the creation of domestic
forces in favor of change” (114).
Regarding a possible concept of corruption as
it relates to particularism and patrimonialism, Mungiu-Pippidi says that “in a society dominated by particularism,
it is more convenient for individuals to try to accede to the privileged group
or to become clients of influential patrons tan to engage in a long-term battle
to change the rule of the game to ethical universalism. In such
societies, there is no tradition of association between equals, since trust is
particularistic and is built on clans, patrons, and clients. Attempts to change
this are bound to have high costs with few immediate returns. Any progress
toward ethical universalism would threaten the existing order, and the
predators and patrons who would fight against such progress are likely to be
greater in number, richer, and better placed in the society than in the new
horizontally structured associations” (109).
No hay comentarios.:
Publicar un comentario
If you have an important question, please e-mail me. These comments are not a reliable form of communication.