Semana 4: Ideal and Non-Ideal Theory
John Rawls´ Theory of Justice: Normative Ideal Theory: Works out a conception of justice in response
to the human condition, which includes moderate
scarcity and limited altruism (Rawls
TJ: §22). Principles of justice serve
the purpose of establishing how conflicting claims should be adjudicated;
Different people have different needs, ends and goals, whose pursuit requires
material resources. So principles of justice are normative because they
determine how resources should be fairly distributed among people. They are
ideal because the theory has two core assumptions: (i) all relevant agents
comply with the demands of justice applying to them; and (ii) natural and
historical conditions are favourable – i.e., society is sufficiently
economically and socially developed to realize justice (Rawls TJ: 8, 215; Law
of P: 4–6). According to Rawls Ideal and non-ideal theories must be related: non-ideal
theory presupposes ideal theory, ‘[f]or until the ideal is identified, at least
in outline … non-ideal theory lacks an objective, an aim, by reference to which
its queries can be answered’ (Rawls Law of P: 90).
Central Problem: Most of the
normative discussion about justice is set by John Rawls´ theory of justice.
Some object this theory by its perceived inability to have an impact on
real-world politics. Is the methodology of ideal theory appropriate for
developing normative prescriptions for public institutions? Is there clarity
about the proper nature of political philosophy (political theory) and its
ability to guide action in real-world circumstances? In the end, is the dispute
legitimate or are they talking past each other?
Central Thesis: There are
three ways in which this discussion could be framed (see below). Valentini believes that only (i) and (iii)
make any sense. Non-ideal theory sets the scope of ideal as far as we frame
issues of compliance and issues of political reform. In any case, even
accepting the importance of (i) and (iii), “there is no right answer to the
question of whether a normative political theory should be ‘ideal’ or ‘non-ideal’
(meaning more or less realistic). The types of idealizations that are
appropriate, and what facts ought to be taken into account in the design of
normative principles depend on the particular question the theory itself is
meant to answer.” (662)
Interpretation
|
Definition/Problem
|
Semantics of
the dispute
|
|
i
|
Full-compliance/partial-compliance
Types
of subjects
|
Full compliance: Agents comply with the demands
of justice (655)
Partial compliance: Agents act unjustly. So the
problem becomes: ‘What ought we to do in circumstances where others do not do
their part?’ There are three options
·
More than the fair share
·
Fair share
·
Less than the fair share
What
duties and obligations apply to us in situations of partial compliance as opposed
to situations of full compliance
|
Problems of
partial compliance are important and inform ideal theory. But conditions are
set by the particularities of cases (656). Individuals ought to do what is
reasonably within their power to respond to existing injustice. So crucial
task is to flesh out what the ‘reasonableness’
constraint amounts
to (656).
|
ii
|
Realist/utopian
Types
of feasibility
|
Utopian: The main ‘job’ of the political
philosopher is not to discover what we should do,
but
rather to discover what we should ‘think’ (Cohen Rescuing: 268).
Realist: They focus in the circumstances
of real politics rather than in the formal circumstances of justice (659).
Alas, political philosophy should give much greater attention to existing
power-structures, and drop implausibly optimistic assumptions about human
nature, such as Rawlsian full compliance. Priority in politics shouldn’t be
justice but rather order, security and peace.
More or less realistic: Either Rawls´ mistake is to
neglect other political ideals like legitimacy, peace and security (while
obsessing with justice); or Rawls’ mistake is his failure to take into account
all those facts that are relevant to theorizing about justice as a real
social ideal, encompassing the most important dimensions of political value.
Should
feasibility considerations constrain normative political theorizing? And, if
so, what sorts of feasibility constraints should matter?
|
The dispute is
not legitimate, as they are talking past each other: “whether a normative
political theory is sufficiently ‘fact-sensitive ⁄ realistic’ or
not depends on
its intended aim and question. This, in turn, suggests that the ‘debate’ between
more or less realistic theories is somewhat misconstrued. Realists and
Rawlsian liberals are not in disagreement about how to answer the same
question. Rather, they seem to be more aptly seen as answering different
questions. The former are looking for principles which are likely to be
effective here and now, the latter seek to develop theories
capable of
identifying the full extent to which the world in which we live is failing
with respect to a grand social ideal.” (660)
|
iii
|
End-state/transitional
Types
of consequences from justice
|
End-state: sets out a long-term goal for institutional reform
(660).
Reform and transition: ‘asks how this long-term goal might be achieved, or
worked toward, usually in gradual steps’
Should
normative political theory aim at identifying an ideal of societal
perfection, or should it focus on transitional improvements without
necessarily determining what the ‘optimum’ is?
|
Both positions
have a point. On the one hand, Sen is correct in arguing that, strictly
speaking, end-state
principles are
not necessary to make justice-comparisons, and that comparisons allowing us
to identify justice-improvements have not been given the attention they
deserve. On the other hand, Simmons is probably right in insisting that
‘ideal’ normative considerations
should in part
influence our choice of paths for justice-improvements (662).
|
Tarea: Leer con
atención el artículo de Sleat sobre la diferencia entre justicia y legitimidad:
Contestar las
siguientes preguntas:
1. ¿En qué sentido para el pensamiento post-rawlseano justicia y
legitimidad son lo mismo?
2. ¿Por qué según Sleat confundir justicia con legitimidad ha sido
terrible para el pensamiento liberal?
3. ¿Qué es lo que hace tan particular o especial a la concepción de
legitimidad (comparada con la de justicia)?
Otros Recursos:
No hay comentarios.:
Publicar un comentario
If you have an important question, please e-mail me. These comments are not a reliable form of communication.